Divorcing Marriage: Unveiling the Dangers in Canadas New Social Experiment
by Douglas Farrow, Dan Cere ISBN: 0773528954
Post Your Opinion | | A Review of: Divorcing Marriage: Unveiling the Dangers in Canada's New Social Experiment by Martin LoneyThe debate over same-sex marriage has been loud but less than
sophisticated. Proponents have tried to betray their critics as
intolerant bigots, eager to stomp on their human rights, but as the
contributors to this collection eloquently demonstrate, there are
powerful reasons to question the sudden rush to transform an ancient
institution.
Five years ago the House of Commons reaffirmed the traditional
definition of marriage by a massive 216 to 55 majority. Darrel Reid
and Janet Epp Buckingham, recall then Justice Minister Anne McClellan's
unequivocal declaration that the government had no intention of
changing the law: "The definition of marriage as a union between
one man and one woman is found in the common law of our country."
McClellan suggested time might be more usefully spent on "debating
other issues as opposed to that on which there is clarity in the
law."
McClellan was right to identify the institution of marriage as
rooted in common law, yet courtesy of the extraordinary arrogance
of the Canadian judiciary, it is now being redefined by the state
in the name of a spurious human rights claim. Many MPs, including
McClellan, formerly an acting dean of law at the University of
Alberta, have suddenly discovered that far from being an issue on
which there is no need for debate, marriage is not after all the
description of a relationship between a man and a woman. Marriage
is no longer to be rooted in social reproduction. Marriage can also
embrace relationships between people of the same sex who have no
inherent reproductive capacity.
Daniel Cere, in his contribution, highlights the way in which
parliament's role was marginalised, with the acquiescence of the
government, as judges used the Charter to embrace changes that had
previously been anathema to the overwhelming majority of Canadians.
In 2003 a parliamentary committee began hearings on the possible
redefinition of marriage, following court cases in Ontario, Quebec
and BC that challenged the traditional definition. The Ontario Court
of Appeal had no intention of waiting for elected politicians to
address the question. In June it struck down the traditional
definition, calling marriage the "union of two persons."
The Chrtien government immediately abolished the parliamentary
committee.
Paul Martin is now committed to driving through legislation that
will, as University of Alberta law professor, F.C. Decoste argues,
constitute a major assault by the state on civil society. Marriage
does not have its origins in government but in civil society. Driven
by a belief in the desirability of social engineering, the judiciary
and the executive propose to claim and transform the institution,
even in the absence of popular support, for such a change. It is a
disturbing trend: "the subject of the social-engineering state
is a vulnerable subject. The subject's values and practices and the
institutions through which it constructs its life story, are always
open to state surveillance and sometimes management." The
extending reach of the modern state might be dressed in progressive
rhetoric but at root it is increasingly totalitarian.
The philosophical basis for the emerging legal consensus, Cere
argues, can be found in close relationship theory, an approach that
captures the preening narcissism that lies at the heart of much
contemporary progressive' thinking. Cere's summary bears repeating:
"A pure relationship is one that has been denuded of any goal
or end beyond the intrinsic emotional, psychological, or sexual
satisfaction that the relationship brings to the adults involvedIn
so far as marriage itself is drawn into this new culture of intimacy,
it is placed on a level playing field with all other long term'
sexual partnerships. Severed from its historic roots in sex difference,
permanence, and children it is made more pliable, open to constant
renegotiation, easily contracted and easily dissolved." The
idea that marriage is a lifetime commitment, centred on the altruistic
task of nurturing children can scarcely compete with this agenda
of permanent gratification. McGill ethicist, Margaret Sommerville,
captures the essence of the proposed change: "accepting same-sex
marriage necessarily means accepting that the social institution
of marriage is intended primarily for the benefit of the partners
to the marriage, and only secondarily for the children born into
it."
It is endlessly claimed by supporters of same-sex marriage that
what is demanded is simply an equality right. In truth the demand
is to redefine an ancient institution in ways that strip it of its
original meaning. Every adult Canadian has the right' to marry, but
marriage is with a person of the opposite sex. Co-editor Douglas
Farrow, McGill professor of Christian thought, captures the issue:
"If marriage is the union of a man and a woman, the freedom
to marry the person of one's choice cannot mean the freedom of a
man to marry a man." It is equally claimed that allowing
individuals of the same sex to marry' will in no way change the
institution for opposite sex partners. This is disingenuous; Cere
quotes gay and lesbian rights theorist, Ladelle McWhorter: "if
same-sex couples get legally married, the institution of marriage
will change, and since marriage is one of the institutions that
support heterosexuality and heterosexual identities, heterosexuality
and heterosexuals will change as well." What is at issue in
this debate is not tolerance of differences but the demand for
approval and endorsement of lifestyles and relationships that many
Canadians reject. More specifically, we are engaged in a battle to
define the public meaning of marriage. Is it to remain consistent
with its historic sense or is it to be hijacked and transformed
into something different to appease the very small number of Canadians
who wish to describe their same-sex relationship as a marriage'?
The suggestion that the proper response to an imperious judiciary
lies in invoking the notwithstanding' clause has been met with
outrage and portrayed as an attack on the Charter. Ted Morton argues
section 33 was inserted precisely to ensure the ultimate authority
of parliament and to reign in an activist judiciary. Its use in
this case would be particularly apt since the broader history of
judicial intervention in the same-sex issue rests not on the explicit
provisions of the Charter, whose framers excluded sexual orientation
from the equality rights section, but on the courts insisting on
reading in' such provisions. Morton argues that whatever one's views
on the merits of the particular case there is an overwhelming
argument for ensuring that sovereignty on such important questions
rests with the people, whether through parliament or a referendum
rather than a handful of judicial appointees. Morton argues
convincingly that advocates of same-sex rights' ultimately distrust
democracy, preferring instead to wage an apparently endless,
taxpayer-funded battle through the courts: "Isn't the whole
unspoken premise of this affair that the Canadian people can no
longer be trusted to decide such issues?"
Many readers will disagree with this book's conclusions but few
will come away without a much clearer grasp of the issues at stake
and the far-reaching implications of a decision that appears
inevitable.
|